Humanness Symposium II
Where Humanization Begins and Where It Ends:
  The Case of the Human Family

Toomas Gross

An examination of humanness in terms of the development and changes in the past, present, and future of the social and cultural implications of human biology, concentrating on the emergence of human family and kinship, or the sense of "belonging" to certain social or socio-biological networks.

Toomas Gross is a social anthropologist at Cambridge, England.


Introduction

My aim in this essay is to look at what constitutes humanness from the perspective of social anthropology. I will not be concerned so much with human prehistory and the evolution of Homo sapiens as a species, which is the area of expertise of paleontologists and archaeologists, but rather with the social aspects of being human; that is, the development and changes in the past, present, and future of the social and cultural implications of human biology. It must also be stressed that there exist not only countless and divergent ways of looking at humanness, depending on the angle of a particular reference-discipline, but there also exist numerous and often contradictory perspectives within the confines of the same discipline. All must be taken into account if we want to understand what really constitutes humanness, but all cannot be taken into account within the given limitations of time and space, as well as our own limited capacity to grasp the true nature of things.

From the many aspects of the "humanization" process, I have chosen to concentrate upon the emergence of human family and kinship, or, in other words, the sense of belonging to certain social or socio-biological networks. The feeling of belonging is, to my mind, one of the constituting features of our being human that manifests itself on various alternative or simultaneous levels–for example, we belong to a family, to a social or cultural group, to a nation, to a species, to God, etc.

Belonging is to a large extent, although not exclusively, a matter of definition. To define ourselves we need both otherness and sameness. We often, if not always, define ourselves in relation to others, 1 in order to have a sense of belonging, we need someone with whom we can identify (or in some respects identical) to ourselves. The other can be constructed on various levels, and the other on one level can be part of the self on the next. A well-known Arabic saying describes this reality–"me and my brother against my cousin; me, my brother and my cousin against other Arabs; me, my brother, my cousin and all Arabs against the whole world."2

I think that it was not so much the emergence of the distinction between "me" and "other", but the emergence of the distinction between "us" and "them" which came after that, which was one of the most important and crucial steps in the beginning of humanity. That is, the perception of oneself not just as an individual, but as a member of a group (in the context of the present essay–a family) as opposed to another group. Animals are probably also capable of perceiving the individual self and otherness, and there are various species that are capable of perceiving it on a group level), but the transformation of this perception from a biological to a cultural and social phenomenon, the development of the sense of belonging, is what "humanizes" humans.

I will look at belonging in the sphere of kinship, a traditional domain of research in social anthropology. Kinship gives us the context for finding answers to the questions of who we are and what we are, and to whom we belong. Descent, a particular aspect of kinship, is an important phenomenon that produces continuity in the society, establishes the connection between generations, and defines the universe of significant and insignificant others. Kinship defines, connects and separates both biological and social roles. As shown by numerous anthropological studies, in many societies these roles do not necessarily coincide. For instance, within the concept of parenthood, which has been one of the key-issues in the study of kinship, a distinction between social and biological parenthood has been made. That is, in many societies distinct persons are responsible for the different social and biological roles of parenting.

In the present essay, I will first speculate on human social evolution and the emergence of family and kinship reckoning in general. Then I will look at the different cultural manifestations of kinship, drawing upon various classical anthropological studies, to illustrate that the way we understand who we are and what we are is culture-specific and not universal; thus when we are talking about "what constitutes humanness" space should be left for cultural relativism–that is, our conclusions and concepts should not be hastily imposed to other cultures. I will conclude with a hypothetical visualization of the end of humanization and kinship, which the so-called New Reproductive Technologies or assisted procreation might bring. The New Reproductive Technologies have challenged the Euro-American understanding of kinship as the domain which unites biological and social roles (adoption being the exception, of course), and have made posing the question "What is the connection between who we are and what we are?" more relevant (Abrahams 1990: 131).

Humanization begins: The emergence of human family

One of the main problems of the evolutionary theory of man is the reconciliation of the two contradictory conclusions drawn from the knowledge we have. As Geertz (1973: 114) claims, human evolution is often seen as a continuous process. Indeed, one of the main ideas of Darwin was the continuity of evolution–natura non facit saltum, as he claimed (cf. Ingold 1991: 23). There are no jumps in the evolutionary chain within the process as a whole, or in the evolution of an individual species. Yet, the difference between man and animal is not just of degree, but also of kind. There is a great difference between man and our nearest evolutionary relative the great apes. Only humans have culture. Only humans have values, consciousness, conscience and the sense of history. It appears that evolution has indeed made a great jump. How does one reconcile these two points of view–the continuity of evolutionary process and man’s remarkable difference from animals? For many decades the reigning solution of the "origin-of-culture problem" has been what might be called the "critical point" theory, a term used first by Alfred Kroeber. According to Geertz (1973: 115), this term postulates that "the development of the capacity for acquiring culture was a sudden, all-or-none, quantum-leap type of occurrence in the phylogeny of the primates." At some specific moment in history, the hominidization or the humanization of one branch of the primate line took place. We don’t know what happened. It was portentous, but in genetic or anatomical terms probably a quite minor organic alteration. This change, presumably in the brain’s cortical structure, enabled an animal whose parents had not been competent, in Kroeber’s words, "to communicate, to learn and to teach, to generalize from the endless chain of discreet feelings and attitudes; to be competent." This whole process of the creation of modern man’s capacity for producing and using culture was a marginal quantitative change, giving rise to a radical qualitative difference. Kroeber compared it to the freezing of water, which can be reduced degree by degree without any loss in fluidity until it suddenly solidifies at 0 degrees Celsius. (Geertz: ibid.).

There were three major considerations that led to and supported the critical point theory. First, a tremendous gap existed between the mental abilities of man and his closest living relatives, the great apes. Second, language, symbolization, abstraction, etc. seemed to be an all-or-none, yes-or-no phenomenon. One either spoke or one did not, made tools or did not, imagined demons or did not–half-religions, half-arts, half-languages do not seem to exist. And third, there was the more delicate problem of what is usually called the psychic unity of mankind–that is, the absence of important differences in the nature of the thought process among the various living races of mankind (Geertz 1973: 115-116).

Theories of human social evolution

Human social evolution is usually presented as a teleological sequence of various stages, which often also represent different contemporary forms of societies. Evolutionary thought emerged already in Ancient Greece and Rome. In the 4th century BCE, Dikaiarchos, for example, divided human societies into three groups–hunter-gatherers, pastoralists, and agriculturalists. In the 1st century BCE Lucretius in his poem De rerum natura reflected upon the development of lively and lifeless nature.

During the Enlightenment, the Euro-Christianity-centered conceptualization of the world, prevalent throughout the Middle Ages, was replaced with a different, still simplistic inquiry into the human past. In 1789, Adam Ferguson in his An Essay on the History of Civil Society distinguished between three stages of development of human society: savages, barbarians, and civilization (although, in contrast to this spirit of the Enlightenment Rousseau sanctified the noble savage). By the second half of the 19th century the study of human prehistory, both biological and social was prolific, due in large measure to the emergence of Darwin’s evolutionary theory, which had a great impact on social scientific reasoning. It was at this time, more or less, that anthropology as a separate academic discipline was born.

Early evolutionary anthropology was primarily concerned with the development of different types of societies and kin-systems, as well as the origin of marriage and family. In 1861, Sir Henry Maine published his Ancient Law in which he compared the British Victorian judicial system with the Indian one; claiming that the former was based on contract and the latter on status. In 1871, Sir Edward B. Tylor in his Primitive Culture practically repeated what Ferguson had claimed a century earlier: that human culture had developed through three stages–savagery, barbarism, and civilization. But Tylor went further, claiming that similar contemporary types of societies could be regarded as being on different levels of social evolution, and that those on the lower levels–hunter-gatherers in particular–were survivals from the past. For Tylor this meant that if we were to study the !kung of Africa or Austrailian Aboriginals we would have an idea of what life was like for our ancestors ten thousand years ago; that is, they are windows to our prehistory.

Other influential figures of early anthropology who touched upon the social evolution of man were Bachofen, McLennan, Morgan, and Engels among others, who will be introduced later. Many of the early theories of human social development were dualistic in nature, viewing the whole process as a teleological transition from one mode of organization to another. Sir Henry Maine, as already mentioned, spoke about the transition from status to contract; Tönnies about the transition from Gemeinschaft to Gesellschaft; Durkheim about the transition from mechanic solidarity to organic solidarity.

Contemporary anthropologists usually differentiate between four stages in human social evolution–hunter-gatherers, agriculturalists, pastoral societies,3 and industrial states.4 As will be shown later, the emergence of the hunting way of life was crucial for the development of early family, but it must be made clear here that contemporary hunter-gatherers have little in common with the pre-historic ones. The perception of hunter-gatherers is loaded with stereotypes and stigmatizations, which were already developed by early social philosophers and anthropologists, and which ranged from the noble savage (Rousseau) to the survivals of the past (Tylor).5 Later anthropologists have challenged many of the common stereotypes regarding hunter-gatherers. Tylor’s concept of survivals was, of course, naïve, because the history of contemporary hunter-gatherers has been as long as of any other type of human society, and the conditions under which they now live (usually on the periphery of nation states, having been pushed out from their original productive ecological niches) are quite different from those of the past. Contemporary hunting and gathering groups are by no means a window to our prehistory. Nor did they live in seclusion in the past, but had regular contact with other similar groups, or other parallel existing forms of societies.

Anthropologists have also shown that, contrary to what is often believed, the amount of free time from subsistence activities is the greatest among hunter-gatherers, and that hunter-gatherers are not only concerned with the search for food. Malinowski still represented this stagnant view, claiming in his well-known quote that the road from the stomach to the head of the savage is short. The world for the savage, Malinowski argued, was a hazy background in front of which only edible and useful things were clearly distinguished. Marshall Sahlins (1974), on the other hand, calls hunters and gatherers "the first affluent society," claiming that the !kung bushmen in Africa, for example, have only to work 11 days in order to have 100 days free.

The emergence of human family

Besides speculating on human macro-social evolution, early and later anthropologists also studied the evolution of particular human institutions–the family and marriage among others. At this point I will give a short overview of some of these discussions, combined with some more contemporary evidence with regard to these topics.

It is not quite clear when, exactly, the family emerged in the evolution of man. We can locate it roughly, but the exact positioning is a matter of speculation. As Gough (1974: 112) puts it, the most fundamental problem of the origin of family is our ignorance about it. In trying to determine the time of the emergence of family, different authors have proposed periods ranging from 2 million to 100 thousand years ago. In addition we do not know whether it emerged once and for all, or in different places and on different occasions. Nor do we know whether the family emerged before the development of speech and language, or after. As Gough (ibid.) claims, it is quite possible that language and family developed together for a long time.

The problem with studying the origin and evolution of human family, and the phenomena related to it, is that we have three main sources of knowledge–great apes, paleontological fossils and contemporary hunter-gatherers–all of which are imperfect. The great apes of today are not our ancestors and have gone through an evolution as long as and quite different from our own. And while fossils tell us much about the physical aspects of human life, they tell us little about the social aspects. And finally, the contemporary hunter-gatherers cannot be considered windows to our prehistory, as tempting as it may seem so to do.

Judging from the fossils, we can say that the simians that were the ancestors of men, gorillas and chimpanzees lived in various regions in Europe, Asia and Africa about 12-28 million years ago. At the end of the Myocene era, a species called Ramapithecus appeared in Northern India and in Oriental Africa. Ramapithecus can be considered the ancestor of both the last Hominids and modern humans. It was a species of small stature that walked on two feet, had lateral teeth, and used their hands rather than their teeth to break edible things.

From Ramapithecus until the appearance of Homo sapiens about 70 thousand years ago, human evolution passed through many stages. During this process, due to the extensive use of hands by the simians, hunting and warfare developed. Men, starting to concentrate on hunting, covered long distances while lactating women could not do so. This, Gough (1974: 126) believes, produced the first sexual division of labor on the basis of which the human family developed. This initial division of labor in human history was considered so important that Clark (1977: 19) even calls it "one of the mainsprings of human progress."

Some time later, the capacity for language and speech started to emerge. Language was an important factor from the point of view of the development of family and kinship, because it made possible the definition of relatives, significant others, etc. As Clark (ibid.: 20) puts it, the lack of speech was one of the greatest drawbacks of the great apes and was alone sufficient to prevent them from acquiring the elements of culture. Until hominids had developed words as symbols, the possibility of transmitting and accumulating culture hardly existed. For example, man’s pre-linguistic counting ability was only on the level of birds and squirrels. Serious mathematics could develop only with the use of symbols. Clark (ibid.) concludes that speech must have been one of the first indications of humanity. The problem of its study, however, is that it is difficult, if not impossible, to detect the ability for speech from paleontological findings.

The use of fire was another important factor in creating the household and uniting it together into a single physical space, the center of which was fire. Fire also meant the development of the art of cooking which further enforced the division of labor.

Gough (1974: 130) claims that it is not clear when all these developments took place. A climatic change started all around the world about 28 million years ago. Around 12 million years ago, in India and Africa, the branches of pre-humans and the ancestors of chimpanzees and gorillas separated from the same trunk. Around 1.75 million years ago the Southern and Eastern Africa were inhabited by Australopithecus, a small bipedal hominid with erect posture and a brain bigger than that of the simians, who could make tools–although other authors (see Clark 1977: 22) claim that tool-making probably started with Homo habilis. According to Geertz (1973: 117), Australopithecus is also the context of the critical point theory of the origin of culture. This small-brained (about one-third the size of modern humans) proto-man could make tools and hunt. Australopithecus must thus have had an elementary form of culture (or proto-culture). From here Geertz concludes, somewhat surprisingly, that the greater part of human cortical expansion has followed, not preceded, the beginning of culture, which could prove the contrary to what is generally believed–that acquiring culture could still have been a gradual process.

It is unclear, however, whether Australopithecus could use fire. The first known use of fire is attributed to the Chinese man (belonging to the line of Pithecantropus), who was discovered in Chukutien, near Beijing, and who lived there during the second glacial era around 500 thousand years ago. Increasing self-awareness probably developed in the later stage of human prehistory. It was not until the Upper Pleistocene era that we get the first evidence of systematic burial of the dead by Middle Paleolithic man. The Neanderthal man, who inhabited caves and used fire in Europe, Africa and Asia 100 - 150 thousand years ago, was probably the first one to develop an increased self-awareness and a belief in the supernatural, which is proven by the fact that he buried his dead ceremonially. The majority of anthropologists believe that by the time of the Neanderthals the household way of life, the family, and language had also already been developed.6 The problem with the Neanderthals, however, according to common knowledge in paleontology, is that they are off the main track of human evolution and therefore not the ancestors of modern man (although recent paleontological findings near Lisbon in Portugal this year might disprove this belief).

Self-adornment and the practice of art appeared only at the end of human prehistory, at a time of rapid technological innovation. Indeed Homo sapiens sapiens were the first to practice self-adornment (Clark 1977: 21).

The emergence of the hunting way of life, which eventually led to the sexual division of labor, is often seen as the trigger in the development and evolution of human families. Clark Howell (1973: 91) claims that the development of the hunting way of life, even at a very unsophisticated level of adaptation, set very different requirements on early human populations. It led to markedly altered selection pressures and was, in fact, responsible for profound changes in human biology and culture. This adaptation was a critical factor in the emergence of many fundamentally human institutions. Some of the changes, which represent the human way of life, would include:

  1. a greatly increased home range and the defense of territorial boundaries to prevent infringement upon the food sources;
  2. a band organization of interdependent and affiliated human groups of variable but relatively small size;
  3. (extended) family groupings with prolonged male-female relationships, incest prohibition, rules of exogamy for mates, and subgroups based on kinship;
  4. the sexual division of labor;
  5. altruistic behavior; including, food-sharing, mutual aid, and co-operation; and
  6. linguistic communities based on speech.

Washburn and Lancaster (1973) also express the idea that the hunting and gathering way of life led to the emergence of human family. They (1973: 68) claim that the genus Homo has existed for some 600 thousand years, and that the entire evolution of the earlier Homo erectus to existing races took place during the period when man was a hunter. Furthermore Washburn and Lancaster (1973: 79) state that when males hunted and females gathered the rewards were shared among those in the group; this habitual sharing among a male, a female and their offspring is the human family. According to this view, the human family is the result of the reciprocity of hunting, which is formed through the addition of a male to the pre-existing mother-plus-young social group of the monkeys and apes. This view of the family also offers a reason for incest taboos. If the function of the addition of a male to the group is economic, then the male who is added must be able to fulfil the role of a socially responsible provider. In the case of the hunter this necessitates a degree of skill in hunting and a social maturity that is attained some years after puberty. The necessary delay in the assumption of the role of provider for female and young can be achieved only by an incest taboo, because brother-sister mating would result in the presence of an infant while the brother was still years away from effective social maturity. Father-daughter incest would produce a baby without adding another providing male; this is quite different from taking a second wife, which, if permitted, is allowed only for those males who have shown they are able to provide for more than one female. Further, Washburn and Lancaster (1973: 80) argue that the fact that the organization of the family may be attributed to the hunting way of life is also supported by ethnography–that is, the institution of family was not necessary in a society in which each individual gets his or her own food.

The transfer from hunting and gathering to an agricultural mode of life brought about many revolutionary processes that affected the development of human family. As Clark (1977: 23) puts it, the transition to more effective basis of subsistence was crucial in the evolution of humanity. In every part of the world farming has preceded and formed a platform on which civilizations have built themselves. Having this in mind, Gordon Childe formulated the concept of the Neolithic Revolution comparable in importance with the Industrial and Scientific Revolutions.

Hunter-gatherers and tribal societies differ qualitatively–the first are basically concerned with food-collection, the latter with food-production. Transfer from food-collection to food-production brought along many important social changes–a sedentary mode of life, the growth of population, the growth of productivity etc. These took place during the Neolithic era and so rapidly, that this transformation is sometimes also called Neolithic paradox.

Archaeological data show that from 40 - 15 thousand BCE man was mostly dedicated to hunting big game, and from 15 - 8 thousand BCE to collecting plants and fishing. The transfer from food-collection to food-production (i.e. growing plants and domesticating animals) took place in the Neolithic era, first in the Middle East, later in Far East, Africa and independently on the American continent. What caused such a dramatic change in the mode of life occurring independently in many parts of the world? Since there could have been no internal push from hunting and gathering to cultivating land (on the contrary – cultivation of land is much more labor demanding), the cause had to be found in the change of environmental conditions. One such change could have been a global increase in population, during which some groups would have been pushed to less productive areas where they had to start growing things themselves. Archaeological findings, however, do not support this theory and a demographic explosion should have followed, and not preceded, the transfer from food-collection to food-production. Some archaeologists have claimed that the change of weather to being seasonal may have also been a factor.

Whatever the cause of the change, the fact of the matter is that food-production meant a sedentary mode of life and this indeed caused a demographic explosion, which had an enormous impact on the structure of human family. Speculatively, there are various reasons why a sedentary mode of life might have caused this demographic explosion:

  1. infanticide ended–earlier nomadic families had to carry their children with them, and some of them were killed to increase the group’s mobility;
  2. changes in female physiology–more food for the newborn meant that breast-feeding stopped earlier, fertility arrived at an earlier age, and the interval between pregnancies shortened; thus the number of births increased;
  3. changes in female anatomy–the ratio between fat and muscle in the female body increased which in turn increased fertility;
  4. fewer wars and conflicts–fewer men died, which meant more men in the group.

The stages in the evolution of human family

Besides trying to localize the emergence of human family in the evolution of man, anthropologists have also tried to speculate on the different stages through which the human family has evolved. McLennan and Morgan were especially influential in this respect.

McLennan, in his Primitive Marriage (1865), suggested that in the beginning there was promiscuity, which gave way to a system in which kinship was traced through females only (which he thought to have been the case in ancient Greece); this in turn gave way to tracing kinship through males only (as in ancient Rome); and finally, to monogamy and tracing kinship through both males and females.

Lewis Henry Morgan and his Ancient Society (1877) had an even greater impact. In fact, Friedrich Engels was particularly influenced by his views and tried to determine, on the basis of the evolution of human family, at which point in human history inequality between men and women emerged. In the inequality between sexes Engels saw the origin of later economic inequality.

Morgan, followed by Engels, believed that after initial promiscuity, people began prohibiting sexual relations between the generations of parents and children, while continuing to allow sexual relations between sisters and brothers. This family was called "consanguine." Later, relations were also prohibited between sisters and brothers; although before this there was an intermediary type of family, where a group of sisters, or other women who were relatives, married a group of brothers or related men from another band (the Punaluan family). The monogamous family is a quite recent phenomenon. The sequence proposed by Morgan and Engels is as follows:

  1. Blood kin family–or sexual promiscuity–the type of family where men and women were completely equal;
  2. Consanguine family–a group marriage characterized by sexual relations between sisters and brothers;
  3. Punaluan family–a group marriage where a group of sisters or other women who were relatives married a group of brothers or related men from another band. According to Engels, the roles of men and women in this family type were still equal–economic decisions were made together, male and female activities were equally estimated. This was a communistic household that Engels, following Bachofen, believed was matriarchal;
  4. Monogamous family–characterized by a strong marriage tie and inequality between men and women.

Morgan derived his conclusions from the analysis of kinship terminology. In fact Morgan based his whole theory on kinship nomenclature. For example, if a system designated many men father, other than the actual biological father, then, Morgan reasoned, it could be that some custom of group marriage prevailed, in which many men might be the putative genitors of the child and hence be addressed as father by it (Fox 1974: 19).

Morgan, like his contemporary Tylor, also divided the advances of social organization into three stages: savagery (hunter-gatherers), barbarism (settled agriculture) and civilization (with more advanced agriculture). This division is more or less accepted by contemporary scholars. However, his theory of the stages of the evolution of human social life–from promiscuity through different forms of family to monogamy–has been rejected.

Matriarchy or patriarchy?

Early discussion on family was also concerned with whether the Ursozium, or early society, was matriarchal or patriarchal. Maine in his Ancient Law (1861) talked about the patriarchal joint-family–the family of fathers and sons holding property in common, the main kinship unit in India and, in Maine’s opinion, the original form of the Indo-European family. Some of the major early anthropologists, however, predicated the idea that the Ursozium was matriarchal, i.e. that motherright preceded fatherright. Bachofen in his Das Muterrecht (1861) and also McLennan in his Primitive Marriage (1865) were especially influential in this respect. They backed their idea of initial matriarchy with the claim that, since early family and marriage developed in the conditions of sexual promiscuity, which meant fatherhood was not always detectable, the role of mother/woman in the family and kinship system had to be much more important than that of father/man.

However convincing Bachofen’s and McLennan’s theory may be, there is no real evidence for it. Anthropologists have described no truly matriarchal societies, neither in the past, nor in the present, although some have claimed that the Iroquois Confederation might have been matriarchal, as the deputies of the Confederation–sachems– were allegedly nominated by women. But as Morgan, who first studied the Iroquois Confederation himself, admitted, there was no real equality between the sexes (Gough 1974: 116). Commenting upon the contemporary societies, Gough also claims, that although it is true that in some matrilineal societies (like the Hopi of Arizona and the Ashanti of Ghana) men exercise little authority over their wives (among the Nayar, men and women can even live apart), it is still always the man (if not the biological father then another male relative) who exercises control over women and children.

Family and culture

I’ve gone through some of the theories of the emergence of the family. But as I mentioned at the beginning of the lecture, the evolution of family has also taken cultural lines, directions and trajectories. The world is becoming more homogenious, but let’s say your look fifty years back and we see that there were different types of families in different cultures. So we can talk about universals of family, but we can also talk about the cultural particularities.

Family and its cultural universals

Throughout its evolution the family took on particular cultural forms, but it also has developed certain universal dimensions. According to Gough (1974: 115), the family in all times and cultures seems to imply four universals:

  1. there are rules that prohibit sexual relations between the close relatives;
  2. there is a sexual division of labor;
  3. marriage is a socially acknowledged and long-lasting relationship between man and woman; and
  4. the men usually have higher status than women (i.e. women always seem to be the "second sex").

James Fox (1974: 31) suggests that the facts of life with which man has had to come to terms in the process of adaptation, and which are immediately relevant to the study of kinship and marriage, can perhaps be reduced to four basic principles, which in his case are somewhat different from the ones proposed by Gough:

Principle 1 The women have the children.

Principle 2 The men impregnate the women.

Principle 3 The men usually exercise control.

Principle 4 Primary kin do not mate with each other.

I will hereby analyze the emergence of two of these principles–the incest taboo and the distinction between male and female roles.

Incest-taboo

Incest or rather incest-taboo is one of the most universal rules that regulate human societies. According to Lévi-Strauss, the incest taboo is one of the main differences between man and animal. Although various other species also have it, the functioning mechanisms in these cases are usually different from those of man. The universality of the incest-taboo does not mean, however, that incest has never existed in human history. It was quite common among the aristocracy of Ancient Egypt, Peru and Hawaii, whose rulers and aristocracy considered themselves divine, and therefore their blood was not to be mixed with that of a common man or a woman. The only solution was not to marry out of the family, or out of a restricted small group. We now know that in-marriage weakens the population and the individual organisms as well, as genes with potentially lethal mutations, which usually are recessive, and, due to their low frequency, "dormant" in the heterozygotous form, might become homozygotous causing the respective individuals to die. Some even think that extensive in-marriage among the Mayan aristocracy lead to the sudden and mysterious fall of their empire approximately 900 CE. Anthropologists also point out, that although the incest taboo seems to be universal, each culture determines which relationships are defined as incest, or which distant relatives are allowed to marry. In our Western societies, for instance, marriage between cousins is considered incest, while marriage with more distant relatives is accepted. In some other societies, however, the marriage between relatives having a common ancestor as far back as five generations might be considered incest.

Anthropologists and psychologists have proposed various theories explaining for the universality of the incest taboo, and why people already knew to avoid incestuous relationships before they had scientific explanations for its consequences. There are two interesting and contradictory theories, which I will briefly touch upon here. The first belongs to a famous Finnish anthropologist Edward Westermarck. Westermarck’s theory, which is psychological, suggests that since the people who should not intermarry usually grow up together (are of the same family), or know each other from early childhood, they lack sexual attraction towards each other. Arthur Wolf (1968) has proven this with the example of Taiwan in the 1960s. In some Taiwanese regions the daughters of one family are brought up in another, that is together with their prospective husband, who is already decided upon in their early childhood as a contract between the two families. Statistics show that these marriage are, as a rule, not satisfactory for either side, because the man and the woman who grew up together lack sexual attraction towards each other. The same phenomenon has been described in Israeli Kibbutzes. Biologists and ethologists have, by the way, also noticed a lack of sexual attraction among the close kin also in case of some mammals. Biologically this phenomenon is functional–it avoids in-breeding and maximizes genetic variability. Furthermore, it has also been shown, in the study of cases of sexual abuse of daughters by their fathers, that such abuse is more likely if father and daughter have lived separately, than if they have lived together in one family.

Westermarck’s theory and Wolf’s example are based on the assumption that incest-taboo is intrinsic and psychological–people who grow up in a normal family have no inclination for incest. Freud’s theory, on the other hand, is completely contrary to this in many respects. He claims that humans actually strive for incest, but it is the society restricts them. Most of Freud’s theory of sexuality, as we well know, is built upon this drive toward incest, manifested for instance in son’s sexual attraction towards his mother (Oedipus complex), or the daughter’s sexual attraction towards her father (Elektra complex). The drive toward incest is often subconscious and finds its expression in dreams. Malinowski, the founding father of anthropology, followed the same line of thinking to a certain extent. But why would society ban incest? One of the possible answers would be that the incest-taboo is functional. It avoids the disorganization of family and leads to the diminution of sexual competition within the family–preventing the sons and the father from competing for the sexuality of the mother, or the daughters and mother for the sexuality of the father and the family would dissolve. The incest-taboo also leads to exogamy and alliance between different human groups. It is known, for instance, that already early hunter-gatherer groups exchanged women and thus created new alliances with each other.

Male and female roles

As already mentioned above, Engels was particularly interested in the evolution of male dominance over women, and concluded that it emerged with the accumulation of wealth and achieved its extreme manifestation with the rise of the industrial state (Gough 1974: 144). However, the best and most regular patterns of sexual division of labor can be seeb in the case of hunter-gatherer societies. Of the 175 hunter-gatherer societies described by George Murdoch, in 97% of them hunting was exclusively a male activity, while in the remaining 3% it was a mostly male activity. Collection of plants was exclusively female activity in 60% of the hunter-gatherer societies, and in 32% mostly female activity. Fishing was exclusively or mostly male activity in 93% of the societies where it was practiced (Gough 1974: 133).

Anthropologists have proposed many explanations for the almost universal division of male and female roles in different cultures and societies in the past and, in many cases, still in the present. As a whole males had/have productive and females had/have reproductive roles. We may hereunder delimit three speculative theories:

  1. The strength theory–men are simply stronger, and this determines particular activities that require more physical strength, while women have physically less demanding ones. This, however, is not always the case. There are many roles that do not require physical strength, but which in most cultures are reserved exclusively for men; for example, in most hunting-gathering societies men make musical instruments, collect honey, and are religious and political leaders.
  2. The compatibility with child-care theory–it is simply the reproductive capacity of women which determines their roles. But this does not always determine post-natal roles. A good example is Scandinavia and the increasing popularity of paternity leave there.
  3. The expendability theory or minimal sacrifice theory–according to this theory, men acquired the more risky and public roles, and women the less risky and domestic ones. Female reproductive capacity is smaller and more restrained than that of a man (man’s capacity is continuous), and thus losing a woman is more costly to the group than losing a man.

These explanations are based on biology. The fact is however, roles can also have clearly social bases; that is, male and female roles, as well as their character, are also to a large extent determined by socialization. The interplay between biology and society can be well observed in the study of male and female aggressiveness. It is widely accepted that males are more aggressive than females. It is a biological phenomenon caused by the hormones. As has been demonstrated by injecting mice with the male sexual hormone testosterone that causes aggressiveness. But male aggressiveness can also be a result of socialization. The case of a Kenyan tribe Luo illustrates this eloquently. At one particular period of time, more boys than girls were born. Because of the lack of girls, some boys were given female tasks from early childhood and thus socialized as girls. Later studies showed that as adults they were less aggressive than normal men and developed certain characteristics of female personality. So being male or female is not just a matter of biology but also of society and socialization.

Family and its cultural particularities

Despite its cultural universals, family and the whole domain of kinship is the area which possesses an enormous cultural variation, and proves that the knowledge of who we are and what we are is often based not on biology, but is rather a cultural construct. Some examples of parenthood, family and marriage will help to illustrate this.

Family as a cultural construct

The whole institution of human family itself with all its different functions–as a physical household, as a mechanism uniting different generations, as a basic unit in tracing descent, etc.–is a culturally heterogeneous phenomenon. Anthropologists have distinguished several types of physical structures of the contemporary human family, the most general ones being the following:

  1. The nuclear family – consisting of mother, father and their children;
  2. The composite family – polygamous (polygynous and polyandric) families;
  3. The extended family - different generations (i.e. more than two) living together; and
  4. The joint family - nuclear families of brothers and sisters living together.

Family is also the basic unit for tracing descent. In 1967, Peter Murdoch in his World Etnographic Sample described more than 800 societies and their kinship systems. According to his results, 36% of the societies could be characterized by bilateral kinship, 61% by unilineal (among them 47% were patrilineal and 14% matrilineal), 3% are characterized by double descent.

In matrilineal societies mother’s brother invests to his nephew. Anthropologists have claimed that it is so because, as in matrilineal societies extramarital relationships are common, the probability of him being the father of the children of his wife decreases. However, the man can be sure that his sister is of his kin (since their common mother can easily be detected) and thus her children are also related to him.

Marriage as a cultural construct

Marriage is a universal feature of human societies, although at least in one contemporary society (the Nayar in India) no marriage institution allegedly existed until recently. The local family (taravad) consisted of the children and grandchildren of a common female ancestor.

Marriage also has its cultural forms, ranging from monogamy to polygamy, the latter in different forms. Polygamy is far more common than monogamy, as Murdoch (1949) has shown in his earlier study, and most polygamous societies are polygynous (multiple wives). By 1949, he managed to describe 554 societies of which 514 were polygynous.

Group marriage is one particular form of polygamy. It is worth touching upon it here briefly, as its failure in the Western world reveals the importance of context and a definite sense of belonging to humans, and constitutes an introduction to the analysis of the New Reproductive Technologies, which forms the last part of this essay.

As stressed above, anthropologists thought that the early society was promiscuous. Later, group marriage, which anthropologists sometimes call polygynandric marriage, was common as a cultural norm in some remote districts of Uttar Pradesh in the Himalayas (Majumdar 1960). Such marriages seem to have been an adaptation to particular extreme conditions rather than the result of free choice.

Many recent and contemporary utopists and sects have also predicated promiscuity or group marriage, considering it the only form of sexuality that is based on equality and where jealousy does not exist. Jealousy, however, seems to be unavoidable. We are possessive animals, so keeping group marriages together is a hard work and they usually fail, as Van den Berghe (1983: 77) has shown. Many "experiments" in promiscuity prove this. The famous Oneida family in the US during the last century, which at its peak had more than 500 members, was not devoid of jealousy, or male control, and soon disorganized (see, for example, Carden 1969; Kephart 1976; Muncy 1973). Constantine and Constantine (1973) describe numerous group families in the US, studying altogether 26 groups (6 triads, 16 tetrads, 2 pentads, 2 sextads) and conclude that group marriage does not suit human expectations or needs. 58% of the groups broke up in less than a year, and only 2 groups stayed together for more than 4 years. Only 2 children were born from these formations, and 80% of the members claimed that they felt jealous.

The Israeli Kibbutz, an agricultural community and organized in many respects contrary to shtetl, the Jewish urban community, is also a form of communistic utopia, although not organised so much sexually, as economically and socially (see, for instance, Spiro 1956, 1958; Tiger and Shepher 1975). The aim of the Kibbutz was also to eliminate the family by raising children in a group, thereby abolishing sexual inequality and the sexual division of labor. The utopia worked on all other fronts except the above-mentioned ones (Van den Berghe 1983: 101).

To this point I have reflected on different heterosexual arrangements in Marriage. The fact of the matter is that marriage can also take and has taken place between members of the same gender, and this not only in the context of Western liberalism and social democracy, but also in many other cultures. The Cheyenne Indians had so-called berdache –male transvestites who acted as co-wives. Among the Azande in Africa, soldiers had temporary so-called "boy-wives." Furthermore, homosexuality and heterosexuality have also been periodic within cultures, for example the Etoro in New Guinea believed that giving sperm to women throughout the whole year would decrease their strength and vitality, and so would shift from heterosexual to homosexual arrangements for periods of 200 days. Lesbian marriages have also been described in many cultures of Africa.

Celibacy, or abstinence, has also been practiced periodically in some cultures. Among the Duguni, for instance, men and women avoided sexual relationships for 4-6 years after the birth of a child. This is quite functional since another pregnancy is avoided immediately after the birth of the newborn, so that the mother can invest sufficient time and attention to the newly born child during its critical years.

Conclusion

From the, albeit speculative, perspective of social anthropology we can say that the definition of family has universal and cultural components; it is a biological and cultural phenomenon which appears to adapt to the changes and needs of each particular culture. As people evolve, so do cultures, so does the family. For this reason, we cannot only look at the family from a universalistic perspective, even as we cannot look at humanisation from a universal perspective. In any discussion of the human, we must leave room for cultural relativism. This is especially true as we face one important change, and therefore challenge to the definition of humanness and the family, in Euro-American society today, namely, the New Reproductive Technologies, which is the topic of my next presentation. These technologies challenge our very notions of family, by challenging our ideas about parenthood. Furthermore, they have within them the possibility of challenging our very basic assumptions of what it means to be human.



Footnotes:

1. Such a view dates back to Cooley's looking-glass theory of the self, according to which we look at the reactions of the others to find out what we are like (Cooley 1922). Otherness in this case is used as a mirror that reflects our self. In anthropology, the archaeology of otherness is in many ways based on the assumption posed by Lévi-Strauss that we think in the form of binary oppositions; for instance, in terms of "us and them", "right and wrong", "rational and irrational", "developed and primitive", "logos and mythos", "logic and prelogic", "Culture and Nature", and that this binary mode of thought is universal to all humankind in time and space. return to text 

2. Evans-Pritchard (1987: 281) in his classical study of the Nuer in Africa, for instance, showed that groups of people in conflict may use the strategy of fission and fusion, and depending on the scope of conflict, different local units may fuse and act as one, or distinguish themselves from each other and act separately. Shore (1994: 782) speaks in that case about segmentary process of identity construction, one that connects different orders or ascending "levels" of belonging. Identity is represented as a process of classification involving boundaries of inclusion and exclusion. Amodio (1994: 69) illustrates such multilevel systems simply in the following manner: we can be opposed to you on one level, but together they will be opposed to they on the other one. Thus the distinction between self and other can be blurred and kept in constant fluctuation. return to text 

3. Pastoral societies should, in fact, be considered a dead-end-street of human evolution, an adaptation to certain extreme natural conditions that make agriculture impossible. return to text 

4. An alternative typology is based on political organization. On that basis, bands, tribes, chiefdoms and states are distinguished. return to text 

5. The term "hunter-gatherer" itself has been attacked on various grounds. Radical feminists, for instance, have gone as far as to suggest that the term should be replaced with that of "gatherer-hunter," because in the original phrase hunting, primarily male activity, stands first, and gathering, primarily female activity, second. Hunting, however, is not always the main subsistence activity of these peoples at all. It has been claimed on the basis of Murdoch's descriptions of various societies that around 30% of the contemporary hunter-gatherer groups are mainly concerned with the collection of plants, about 40% with fishing, and 25 % with hunting, while others are not strictly of one distinct type. return to text 

6. As for language, there are also some who claim that already Australopithecus, 2 million years ago, was capable of it (e.g. Hockett and Ascher 1968), while others (e.g. Livingstone 1969) situate it at a much later date - between 50 and 70.000 years ago (cf. Gough 1974: 130). return to text 


ABOUT THIS ARTICLE

Draft 99/12/11
Toomas Gross: Where Humanization Begins and Where It Ends : The Case of the Human Family
Humanness II : Friday May 28, 1999 – Sunday, May 30, 1999
Montréal, Québec

Maximus' Slide-In Menu by Maximus at absolutegb.com/maximus
Submitted and featured on Dynamicdrive.com


LINKS:   Humanness Symposium Home Page
Montreal Lutheran Council Home Page
E-Mail

Top